The COVID-19 Forecasting Project at the University of Oxford is making advanced pandemic simulations of 150+ countries available to the public, and also offer pro-bono forecasting services to decision-makers.
Beeminder's an evidence-based willpower augmention tool that collects quantifiable data about your life, then helps you organize it into commitment mechanisms so you can keep resolutions. They've also got a blog about what they're doing here
Jane Street is a quantitative trading firm with a focus on technology and collaborative problem solving. We're always hiring talented programmers, traders, and researchers and have internships and fulltime positions in New York, London, and Hong Kong. No background in finance required.
B4X is a free and open source developer tool that allows users to write apps for Android, iOS, and more.
Dr. Laura Baur is a psychiatrist with interests in literature review, reproductive psychiatry, and relational psychotherapy; see her website for more. Note that due to conflict of interest she doesn't treat people in the NYC rationalist social scene.
Substack is a blogging site that helps writers earn money and readers discover articles they'll like.
MealSquares is a "nutritionally complete" food that contains a balanced diet worth of nutrients in a few tasty easily measurable units. Think Soylent, except zero preparation, made with natural ingredients, and looks/tastes a lot like an ordinary scone.
AISafety.com hosts a Skype reading group Wednesdays at 19:45 UTC, reading new and old articles on different aspects of AI Safety. We start with a presentation of a summary of the article, and then discuss in a friendly atmosphere.
Metaculus is a platform for generating crowd-sourced predictions about the future, especially science and technology. If you're interested in testing yourself and contributing to their project, check out their questions page
Altruisto is a browser extension so that when you shop online, a portion of the money you pay goes to effective charities (no extra cost to you). Just install an extension and when you buy something, people in poverty will get medicines, bed nets, or financial aid.
Giving What We Can is a charitable movement promoting giving some of your money to the developing world or other worthy causes. If you're interested in this, consider taking their Pledge as a formal and public declaration of intent.
80,000 Hours researches different problems and professions to help you figure out how to do as much good as possible. Their free career guide show you how to choose a career that's fulfilling and maximises your contribution to solving the world's most pressing problems.
Seattle Anxiety Specialists are a therapy practice helping people overcome anxiety and related mental health issues (eg GAD, OCD, PTSD) through evidence based interventions and self-exploration. Check out their free anti-anxiety guide here
.
Support Slate Star Codex on Patreon. I have a day job and SSC gets free hosting, so don't feel pressured to contribute. But extra cash helps pay for contest prizes, meetup expenses, and me spending extra time blogging instead of working.
Also, what does average person mean? If someone gets AIDS at age 15, does that mean they only have a 50% chance of living past 45?
No. Think of it this way: take away the “after getting HIV” part. How long does the average person in the U.S. have to live starting from this point? Well, the median person in the U.S. is 40. Life expectancy at 40 is about 38 more years. So the average person has a life expectancy of about 38 more years But doesn’t mean someone at 15 has a life expectancy of 38 more years: someone at 15 has a life expectancy of 62 more years. It’s the same with HIV. The distribution of number of years that people live after being diagnosed with HIV varies with age of diagnosis, just as the distribution of life expectancy varies for people who haven’t been diagnosed with HIV.
That seems a silly measure, then. What’s the average difference in QALY in HIV vs. non-HIV patients?
That would depend on the quality adjustment part, perhaps even more than the life years part. It would probably be easier to measure the difference in expected lifespan upon learning that you had HIV.
That is, if you learn “Bob is a 30-year-old American male”, you’d expect him to live for about 48 more years if you trust the first Google hit for “actuarial chart”. If you then learned Bob had AIDS, what would your new estimate of his lifespan be, and how would this change with the age/gender of Bob?
EDIT: Of course, this isn’t actually the question you want to ask, because of confounders. It’s still probably the most informative one that’s easy to answer (especially if you care about being ethical while answering the question).
What Daniel suggests would be the measure I’d want as well, and I don’t know what that is.
I would argue, though, that this isn’t a totally silly measure just by virtue of the fact that life expectancy after HIV diagnosis used to be so much lower. The major reason why it’s changed is the development of better medications, not the changing age distribution of the newly-infected. If you are remembering those days and thinking that HIV diagnosis still equals impending death, this can inform you otherwise.
The alcoholism example would be legitimate given Lesswrong-style ideas of timeless decision theory (which I don’t necessarily endorse). If you are able to convince your dad to become a drinker, it is more likely that you have a genetic history of alcoholism, even though the genetic history is not caused by the fact that you have convinced him. This does mean convincing your dad to drink will be assicated with a higher chance that the medicine works.
In fact it can be seen on a variation on the smoker’s lesion problem; only the “drinker’s genetic lesion” is associated with something good (better ability to use the drug) instead of something bad (cancer).
I think that’s just Evidential Decision Theory. Timeless and Updateless Decision Theories are supposed to give the intuitively correct answer to this problem without failing Newcomb’s problem.
You may be right. Still, my point stands; there’s a legitimate decision theory under which the patient’s reasoning is correct.
I wouldn’t exactly call it legitimate, for exactly the reason that under it the patient’s reasoning is correct.
And to reduce the harm, the patient should arrange that his newly-drunk father get AIDS, so that he’ll live another 30 years.
I’m pretty sure TD, UD, and ED would take the knowledge that the father can probably be convinced as evidence that the gene is present. Then, given that the convincing happened, it would be further evidence and ED would say this was good for the patient’s chances of having the treatment work. TD and UD would still say that the convincing might be useful from a VoI perspective.
Of course, given that somebody could be convinced to become alcoholic even without the relevent gene, I’m not sure how much evidence this is. It almost certainly would not be good from any of the three theories if you take into account the costs to (presumably) a loved one.
This doesn’t have to be evidential decision theory, if one presents it not as believing that convincing the father to drink ‘affects’ the effectiveness of the treatment but rather that it gives evidence of what that effectiveness would be so as to allow a more informed decision. That’s entirely causal (though not exactly an efficient or ethical use of your time).
EDIT: Aaand I just noticed that Daniel already said that. But yeah.
Even if that’s a correct application of the Smoker’s Lesion, it only applies to whether the patient is *able* to convince his dad to smoke. Actually doing it wouldn’t be necessary.
Scott – this might be relevant to your interests: http://idlewords.com/2010/03/scott_and_scurvy.htm . The Royal Navy conquered scurvy in 1747, but had lost again by 1900.
Hilarous! Can I use the second example, Scott?
Yes, sure.